93. Limits as tends to .
Let be such a function of that , and let . Then say. As tends to , tends to the limit , and tends to the limit .
Let us now dismiss and consider simply as a function of . We are for the moment concerned only with those values of which correspond to large positive values of , that is to say with small positive values of . And has the property that by making sufficiently small we can make differ by as little as we please from . To put the matter more precisely, the statement expressed by means that, when any positive number , however small, is assigned, we can choose so that for all values of greater than or equal to . But this is the same thing as saying that we can choose so that for all positive values of less than or equal to .
We are thus led to the following definitions:
A. If, when any positive number , however small, is assigned, we can choose so that when , then we say that tends to the limit as tends to by positive values, and we write
B. If, when any number , however large, is assigned, we can choose so that when , then we say that tends to as tends to by positive values, and we write
We define in a similar way the meaning of ‘ tends to the limit as tends to by negative values’, or ‘ when ’. We have in fact only to alter to in definition A. There is of course a corresponding analogue of definition B, and similar definitions in which as or .
If and , we write simply This case is so important that it is worth while to give a formal definition.
If, when any positive number , however small, is assigned, we can choose so that, for all values of different from zero but numerically less than or equal to , differs from by less than , then we say that tends to the limit as tends to , and write
So also, if as and also as , we say that as . We define in a similar manner the statement that as .
Finally, if does not tend to a limit, or to , or to , as , we say that oscillates as , finitely or infinitely as the case may be; and we define oscillation as in a similar manner.
The preceding definitions have been stated in terms of a variable denoted by : what letter is used is of course immaterial, and we may suppose written instead of throughout them.
94. Limits as tends to .
Suppose that as , and write If then and , and we are naturally led to write or simply or , and to say that tends to the limit as tends to . The meaning of this equation may be formally and directly defined as follows:
if, given , we can always determine so that when , then
By restricting ourselves to values of greater than , i.e. by replacing by , we define ‘ tends to when approaches from the right’, which we may write as In the same way we can define the meaning of Thus is equivalent to the two assertions
We can give similar definitions referring to the cases in which or as through values greater or less than ; but it is probably unnecessary to dwell further on these definitions, since they are exactly similar to those stated above in the special case when , and we can always discuss the behaviour of as by putting and supposing that .
95. Steadily increasing or decreasing functions.
If there is a number such that whenever , then will be said to increase steadily in the neighbourhood of .
Suppose first that , and put . Then as , and is a steadily increasing function of , never greater than . It follows from § 92 that tends to a limit not greater than . We shall write We can define in a similar manner; and it is clear that It is obvious that similar considerations may be applied to decreasing functions.
If , the possibility of equality being excluded, whenever , then will be said to be steadily increasing in the stricter sense.
96. Limits of indetermination and the principle of convergence.
All of the argument of §§ 80-84 may be applied to functions of a continuous variable which tends to a limit . In particular, if is bounded in an interval including (i.e. if we can find , , and so that when ). then we can define and , the lower and upper limits of indetermination of as , and prove that the necessary and sufficient condition that as is that . We can also establish the analogue of the principle of convergence, prove that the necessary and sufficient condition that should tend to a limit as is that, when is given, we can choose so that when .
Example XXXV
1. If as , then , , and , unless in the last case .
[We saw in
§ 91 that the theorems of
Ch. IV,
§ 63 et seq. hold also for functions of
when
or
. By putting
we may extend them to functions of
, when
, and by putting
to functions of
, when
.
The reader should however try to prove them directly from the formal definition given above. Thus, in order to obtain a strict direct proof of the first result he need only take the proof of Theorem I of § 63 and write throughout for , for and for .]
2. If is a positive integer then as .
3. If is a negative integer then as , while or as , according as is odd or even. If then and .
4. .
5. , unless . If and , , then the function tends to or , as , according as and have like or unlike signs; the case is reversed if . The case in which both and vanish is considered in Ex. XXXVI 5. Discuss the cases which arise when and more than one of the first coefficients in the denominator vanish.
6. , if is any positive or negative integer, except when and is negative. [If , put and apply Ex. 4. When , the result follows from Ex. 1 above. It follows at once that , if is any polynomial.]
7. , if denotes any rational function and is not one of the roots of its denominator.
8. Show that for all rational values of , except when and is negative. [This follows at once, when is positive, from the inequalities (9) or (10) of § 74. For , where is the greater of the absolute values of and (cf. Ex. XXVIII. 4). If is negative we write and . Then
97.
The reader will probably fail to see at first that any proof of such results as those of Exs. 4, 5, 6, 7, 8 above is necessary. He may ask ‘why not simply put , or ? Of course we then get , , , , ’. It is very important that he should see exactly where he is wrong. We shall therefore consider this point carefully before passing on to any further examples.
The statement is a statement about the values of when has any value distinct from but differing by little from zero. It is not a statement about the value of when . When we make the statement we assert that, when is nearly equal to zero, is nearly equal to . We assert nothing whatever about what happens when is actually equal to . So far as we know, may not be defined at all for ; or it may have some value other than . For example, consider the function defined for all values of by the equation . It is obvious that Now consider the function which differs from only in that when . Then for, when is nearly equal to zero, is not only nearly but exactly equal to zero. But . The graph of this function consists of the axis of , with the point left out, and one isolated point, viz. the point . The equation expresses the fact that if we move along the graph towards the axis of , from either side, then the ordinate of the curve, being always equal to zero, tends to the limit zero. This fact is in no way affected by the position of the isolated point .
The reader may object to this example on the score of artificiality: but it is easy to write down simple formulae representing functions which behave precisely like this near . One is where denotes as usual the greatest integer not greater than . For if then ; while if , or , then and so .
Or again, let us consider the function already discussed in Ch. II, § 24, (2). This function is equal to for all values of save . It is not equal to when : it is in fact not defined at all for . For when we say that is defined for we mean (as we explained in Ch. II, l.c.) that we can calculate its value for by putting in the actual expression of . In this case we cannot. When we put in we obtain , which is a meaningless expression. The reader may object ‘divide numerator and denominator by ’. But he must admit that when this is impossible. Thus is a function which differs from solely in that it is not defined for . None the less for is equal to so long as differs from zero, however small the difference may be.
Similarly so long as is not equal to zero, but is undefined when . None the less .
On the other hand there is of course nothing to prevent the limit of as tends to zero from being equal to , the value of for . Thus if then and . This is in fact, from a practical point of view, from the point of view of what most frequently occurs in applications, the ordinary case.
Example XXXVI
1. .
2. , if is any integer (zero included).
3. Show that the result of Ex. 2 remains true for all rational values of , provided is positive. [This follows at once from the inequalities (9) and (10) of § 74.]
4. . [Observe that is a factor of both numerator and denominator.]
5. Discuss the behaviour of as tends to by positive or negative values.
[If
,
. If
,
. If
and
is even,
or
according as
or
. If
and
is odd,
as
and
as
, or
as
and
as
, according as
or
.]
6. Orders of smallness. When is small is very much smaller, much smaller still, and so on: in other words
Another way of stating the matter is to say that, when tends to , , , … all also tend to , but tends to more rapidly than , than , and so on. It is convenient to have some scale by which to measure the rapidity with which a function, whose limit, as tends to , is , diminishes with , and it is natural to take the simple functions , , , … as the measures of our scale.
We say, therefore, that is of the first order of smallness if tends to a limit other than as tends to . Thus is of the first order of smallness, since .
Similarly we define the second, third, fourth, … orders of smallness. It must not be imagined that this scale of orders of smallness is in any way complete. If it were complete, then every function which tends to zero with would be of either the first or second or some higher order of smallness. This is obviously not the case. For example tends to zero more rapidly than and less rapidly than .
The reader may not unnaturally think that our scale might be made complete by including in it fractional orders of smallness. Thus we might say that was of the th order of smallness. We shall however see later on that such a scale of orders would still be altogether incomplete. And as a matter of fact the integral orders of smallness defined above are so much more important in applications than any others that it is hardly necessary to attempt to make our definitions more precise.
Orders of greatness. Similar definitions are at once suggested to meet the case in which is large (positively or negatively) when is small. We shall say that is of the th order of greatness when is small if tends to a limit different from as tends to .
These definitions have reference to the case in which . There are of course corresponding definitions relating to the cases in which or . Thus if tends to a limit other than zero, as , then we say that is of the th order of smallness when is large: while if tends to a limit other than zero, as , then we say that is of the th order of greatness when is nearly equal to .
7. . [Put or , and use Ex. XXXV. 8.]
8. . [Multiply numerator and denominator by .]
9. Consider the behaviour of as , and being positive integers.
10. .
11. .
12. Draw a graph of the function
Has it a limit as ? [Here except for , , , , when is not defined, and as .]
13. .
[It may be deduced from the definitions of the trigonometrical ratios that if
is positive and less than
then
or
or
But Hence , and . As is an even function, the result follows.]
14. .
15. . Is this true if ?
16. . [Put .]
17. ,.
18. .
19. .
20. How do the functions , , behave as ? [The first oscillates finitely, the second infinitely, the third tends to the limit . None is defined when . See . 6, 7, 8.]
21. Does the function tend to a limit as tends to ? [No. The function is equal to except when ; when , , …, , , …. For these values the formula for assumes the meaningless form , and is therefore not defined for an infinity of values of near .]
22. Prove that if is any integer then and as , and , as .